Discussion about this post

User's avatar
P.D. Magnus's avatar

If you were to characterize the tools of the era as intensional (in contrast to the extensional tools of the previous era) then it would be natural to see its successor as hyperintensional rather than social. To turn that around, the origin of the social era might reach as far back as developments in philosophy of science in the wake of Kuhn.

Expand full comment
Misha Valdman's avatar

That’s compelling. There’s no denying modality’s centrality in the period you cite. And even if possible worlds and counterfactual conditionals weren’t front and center on the value theory side of the discipline, Lewis’s unabashed commitment to modal realism clearly paved the way for moral realism’s resurgence in the early aughts.

But I’d slice it differently. Briefly, I’d say that what followed the empiricist/ordinary language era was the era of reflective equilibrium. First proposed by Goodman in the 1950s, it really took root in the early 1970s with Rawls on the value side and Lewis on the M&E side. That methodology created the applied turn in ethics (Thomson, Singer, etc.) and bled into philosophy as a whole, becoming the dominant approach and one that could be assumed without argument. Sarah and I have an amusing piece on Lewis’s commitment to it and how it ultimately leads what we call "problem nihilism" (https://zworld.substack.com/p/what-if-there-arent-any-problems).

But by the early aughts that method had run its course. The tensions between intuition and principle that it tried to balance proved irreconcilable. Philosophers quietly realized that they had to choose, and, by and large, they chose intuition over principle. Mike Huemer’s Moral Intuitionism (2005) was a canary in the coalmine. And thus the age of intuition-mongering -- of appeal to seemings -- was born.

Expand full comment

No posts